52 pages • 1 hour read
A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Nietzsche contrasts Christianity with Buddhism—which he calls “the only genuinely positive religion to be encountered in history” (27).
He claims that while both Christianity and Buddhism are religions of décadence, Buddhism is superior:
1) Buddhism abandons the concept of “gods” altogether,
2) abandons self-deception in moral concepts,
3) yields to reality by replacing the struggle against the inherent evil of humanity with the struggle against humanity’s suffering,
4) understands, like Nietzsche, that goodness is whatever is positive to life, rather than an end in itself,
5) and promotes egoism as natural.
While Nietzsche believes Buddhism is as much a nihilistic religion as Christianity, he has no desire to insult it in his comparative analysis.
Nietzsche describes Buddhism as stemming from the philosophical elite, viewing its own idea of “perfection” as fully attainable by mortals.
By contrast, Christianity stems from the “lowest” individuals, glorifying grotesquery and self-loathing.
Nietzsche argues that Christianity is a religion that ultimately seeks to tame “beasts of prey” (i.e., the Hyperboreans and those capable of becoming like them) and subjugate them within the masses of lower individuals (29).
By contrast, Buddhism applies itself to a society already civilized by advanced philosophy and seeks to bring it to completion. Here, Nietzsche deliberately describes Europe as “not yet civilized” (29).
Nietzsche lauds Buddhism for having the courage to see suffering as being as much a part of the world as any other experience—free of moral judgment. Christianity, on the other hand, invents demons and sins to explain why suffering is so terrible and to separate the religion from its own idealized, imaginary version of a “perfect” reality.
He acknowledges Christianity’s shrewdness in recognizing that by creating a religion of “love,” its believers would withstand any suffering—even the removal of their own power (30).
Nietzsche argues that the origin of Christianity was not a reactionary force acting against Judaism, but an evolution of it. He labels both Christianity and Judaism as religions with moralities grounded in ressentiment—making Christian antisemitism a further moral corruption born of self-loathing.
Nietzsche lauds the Jewish people for facing fatal odds and making the choice to survive “at all costs,” even if this cost was to “go against nature”—which he argues is a choice that could only have been made by a people free of décadence (32).
Nietzsche argues that any study of Israel’s history should consider itself as being part of the history of a “denaturizing” civilization (32). In Israel’s origins as nation and kingdom, Judaism saw its God as a being to give thanks to—something Nietzsche believes is perfectly normal in any religion.
However, after the fall of the Israeli kingdom, Nietzsche believes this worship turned to fear of sin—which began the denaturizing process and instilled false meaning into what he considers to be blind chance.
Nietzsche argues that the “denaturizing” present in both Christianity and Judaism precedes the mythologizing of sin in “scripture” written by priests.
Harnessing their power to alter the written word and call it the word of God, priests deftly secured the keys to salvation for themselves, producing what Nietzsche calls the “prime axiom: ‘God forgiveth him that repenteth’—in plain English, him that submitteth to the priest” (35).
Nietzsche argues that Christianity repurposed the denaturizing practices of the Jewish tradition for the denaturizing of all things, even the last “natural” concept present in Judaism—the “chosen” Jewish people (35).
Christ became the endgame to the ecclesiasticism of Judaism, representing the self-destruction of priestliness—for this reason (and not for the sins of humanity), the Jewish priests and Romans crucified Christ.
Nietzsche questions whether Christ was cognizant of his own contradictions, though he admits he finds the Gospels difficult to decipher. He makes a passing reference to his youthful enjoyment of Das Leben Jesu (Life of Jesus) by David Strauss, but says he is now too old and serious to care for the contradictions of “tradition” (36).
Nietzsche focuses on the “psychological type” of Christ (37). He criticizes French Semitic scholar Ernst Renan’s psychological characterization of Christ as a hero-type, as this concept supports the notion that one person can be superior to others—which is antithetical to Christianity.
Christianity denaturizes the outer world so it can claim “the Kingdom of God is within you” (37).
Much of The Antichrist deals with comparative analyses of Christianity against other religions—with Nietzsche’s analysis of Buddhism in Sections 20-23 being the most generous. While Nietzsche still accuses Buddhism of being a decadent religion (without much evidence), he lauds it for working to reduce ressentiment rather than encourage it. He views Buddhism as an egoistic, personal religion that transcends concepts of gods and grand moralistic mythologizing to focus on reducing the power one’s suffering.
Nietzsche finds Buddhism’s desire to minimize the power of suffering rather than negate suffering altogether especially appealing. To Buddhists, suffering is not inherently evil, but a natural part of life—the ultimate good. But Buddhism also recognizes that suffering can corrupt the human mind and turn it against life in the name of self-preservation. This learning to accept and overcome corruption is the closest any religion gets to matching Nietzsche’s concept of enhancing the will to power.
Nietzsche’s second comparative analysis focuses on Judaism, from which Christianity originates. While other readings suggest that Nietzsche did not intend to argue for antisemitism in Sections 24-27, it is important to note that he does echo antisemitic assumptions and phrases from the late-19th century. He lauds Judaism for following a people’s “natural” instinct to protect and further perfect their collective identity—a quality he believes is present through Jewish history. However, Nietzsche believes the Jewish people turned into a “denaturizing” people out of a need to survive following the fall of Israel. Christianity, he argues, repurposed this denaturizing process via purging its own followers of the last “natural” instinct of the Jewish people. Nietzsche’s belief changed from an act of survival to an opportunistic consolidation of power by the clergy—placing The Antichrist in the political realm (given the power theologians held in German politics at the time).
Nietzsche begins his criticism of Christianity’s origins by framing his reading of Jesus as purely psychological. While he believes such an analysis is crucial to understanding the religion itself, his attack on Ernst Renan’s psychoanalysis of Christ further showcases his distrust of any “theological” criticism preceding his own. Renan’s popularity in Germany at the time would have reinforced this passage’s German scholasticism.
Plus, gain access to 9,100+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features:
By these authors